Results for 'Kevin Russel Magill'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  8
    Critically Civic Teacher Perception, Posture and Pedagogy: Negating Civic Archetypes.Kevin Russel Magill - 2019 - Journal of Social Studies Research 43 (2):159-176.
    Critical pedagogy is an optimistic approach for achieving transformative agency, which remains an elusive and vital aspect of civic education. Therefore, the purpose of this study was to examine the pedagogical approach of three critically identifying teachers. Specifically, this study was interested in understanding participant teacher critically civic ontological postures. The posture implies an understanding of the power inherent to civic relation and pedagogy. Participant teachers uniquely demonstrated postures that allowed them to address conceptual, personal, and material aspects of civics (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  2.  3
    Examining the Complexity of Pre-Service Social Studies Teacher Dispositions: Ideology, Experience, and Privilege.Kevin Russel Magill - 2023 - Journal of Social Studies Research 47 (3-4):245-262.
    In this piece, the author examined the impact of ideology, experience, and privilege on pre-service Social Studies teacher disposition. Findings suggest that participants conceptually understood injustice and began to critique social antagonisms like whiteness and class. However, they continued reinforcing raced and classed ideologies in their interactions with those outside their group. When faced with the cognitive dissonance between stated ideology and their privileged position, the more liberal participants re-narrativize their political stances to adopt more critical ideological worldviews while maintaining (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  3. Freedom and Experience: Self-Determination Without Illusions.Magill Kevin - 1997 - London: author open access, originally MacMillan.
  4. Freedom and Experience, Self-Determination without Illusions.Kevin Magill - 1999 - Mind 108 (431):590-595.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  33
    Critical historical inquiry: The intersection of ideological clarity and pedagogical content knowledge.Brooke Blevins, Kevin Magill & Cinthia Salinas - 2020 - Journal of Social Studies Research 44 (1):35-50.
    This paper presents the relationship between pedagogical content knowledge and political/ideological clarity as a framework for understanding the nuanced interpretations and applications of critical social studies pedagogy and practice. Using a qualitative case study research design, this study explores the decision-making process of two novice social studies teachers as they decide if and how to utilize critical historical inquiry within their classrooms. Findings indicate that teachers’ use of critical historical inquiry is informed by their subject area consciousness and political and (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  6.  8
    Actions, Intentions, and Awareness and Causal Deviancy.Kevin Magill - 1998 - The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 26:38-52.
    In Davidson's example of causal deviancy, a climber knows that he can save himself from plummeting to his death by letting go of a rope connecting him to a companion who has lost his footing, but the thought of the contemplated act so upsets him that he lets go unintentionally. Causation of behavior by intentional states that rationalize it is not enough for it to count as acting. Therefore, the behavior must be caused in 'the right way' or by the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  7.  3
    Epicurus, determinism and the security of knowledge.Kevin Magill - 1992 - Theoria 58 (2-3):183-196.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  8. Editorial.Kevin Magill - 1993 - Radical Philosophy 65.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  9. Conference Report: The First European Congress of Analytic Philosophy, Aix-en-Provence, 23-26 April 1993. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1993 - Radical Philosophy 65.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  10.  12
    Sorting through citizenship: A case study on using cognitive scaffolding to unpack adolescent civic identity formation.Victoria Davis Smith, Kevin R. Magill, Brooke Blevins & Nate Scholten - 2022 - Journal of Social Studies Research 46 (3):223-235.
    Civic engagement requires individuals to have both knowledge of democratic principles and the skills for enacting change. Acquiring the knowledge and skills necessary for a productive civic life can be difficult for students if they are not provided conceptual scaffolds and opportunities to practice citizenship. We implemented and studied an activity using Westheimer and Kahne's (2004) citizenship typology during a summer civics institute to help students grapple with their understandings of “good” citizenship. We found (1) students appropriated the language of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  11.  20
    Blaming, understanding and justification.Kevin Magill - 2000 - In A. van den Beld (ed.), Moral Responsibility and Ontology. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 183--197.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  12.  40
    Epicurus, determinism and the security of knowledge.Kevin Magill - 1992 - Theoria 58 (2-3):183-196.
    The article criticises various interpretations of Epicurus's claim that belief in determinism is self-invalidating: -/- - 'The man who says that all things come to pass by necessity cannot criticise one who denies that all things come to pass by necessity, for he admits that this too happens of necessity.' - -/- especially Ted Honderich's argument that the real force of the Epicurean claim is that if belief acquisition is causally necessitated, we will be excluded from possible facts and inquiries (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  13. The Idea of a Justification for Punishment.Kevin Magill - 1998 - Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 1 (1):86-101.
    The argument between retributivists and consequentialists about what morally justifies the punishment of offenders is incoherent. If we were to discover that all of the contending justifications were mistaken, there is no realistic prospect that this would lead us to abandon legal punishment. Justification of words, beliefs and deeds, can only be intelligible on the assumption that if one's justification were found to be invalid and there were no alternative justification, one would be prepared to stop saying, believing or doing (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  14.  6
    The Dunayevskaya–Marcuse–Fromm Correspondence, 1954–1978: Dialogues on Hegel, Marx and Critical Theory.Kevin Anderson & Russell Rockwell (eds.) - 2012 - Lexington Books.
    Part one. The Dunayevskaya-Marcuse correspondence, 1954-78: the early letters: debating Marxist dialectics and Hegel's absolute idea; Dunayevskaya's Marxism and freedom and beyond; on technology and work on the eve of Marcuse's One-dimensional man; the later correspondence: winding down during the period of the New Left -- Part two. The Dunayevskaya-Fromm correspondence, 1959-78: the early letters: on Fromm's Marx's concept of man and his socialist humanism symposium; dialogue on Marcuse, on existentialism, and on socialist humanism in Eastern Europe; on Hegel, Marxism, (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15. Electing for Democracy: Proportional Representation and the Left. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1992 - Radical Philosophy 60.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  16. The Economic Legacy: 1979-1992. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1994 - Radical Philosophy 67.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  17. Conservatism. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1991 - Radical Philosophy 59.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  18. Innocence and Experience. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1993 - Radical Philosophy 64.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  19. Marxism, Pluralism and Beyond. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1992 - Radical Philosophy 61.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  20. A.J. Ayer: A Life. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 2000 - Radical Philosophy 100.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  21. A. J. Ayer: Memorial Essays. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1994 - Radical Philosophy 68.
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  22. Beyond the Casiono Economy: Planning for the 1990's. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1990 - Radical Philosophy 55:44.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  23. The Construction of Social Reality. [REVIEW]Kevin Magill - 1997 - Radical Philosophy 83.
  24. Broadbent, Hilary A., 55 Caramazza, Alfonso, 243 Cheney, Dorothy L., 167.Russell M. Church, John Gibbon, James I. L. Gould, R. J. Herrnstein, Peter C. Holland, Gabriele Miceli, Kevin F. Miller, David R. Paredes, David Premack & Robert M. Seyfarth - 1990 - Cognition 37 (301):301.
    No categories
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25.  38
    Scientism: Philosophy and the Infatuation with Science. [REVIEW]Roger Harris, Kevin Magill, Vincent Geoghegan, Anthony Elliott, Chris Arthur, Michael Gardiner, David Macey, Nöel Parker, Alex Klaushofer, Gary Kitchen, Tom Furniss, Christopher J. Arthur, Sadie Plant, Fred Inglis, Matthew Rampley, Alison Ainley, Daryl Glaser, Jean-Jacques Lecercle, Sean Sayers, Keith Ansell-Pearson & Lucy Frith - 1992 - Radical Philosophy 61 (61).
  26. Russell's logical atomism.Kevin C. Klement - 2019 - Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2005.
    A summary of Russell’s logical atomism, understood to include both a metaphysical view and a certain methodology for doing philosophy. The metaphysical view amounts to the claim that the world consists of a plurality of independently existing things exhibiting qualities and standing in relations. The methodological view recommends a process of analysis, whereby one attempts to define or reconstruct more complex notions or vocabularies in terms of simpler ones. The origins of this theory, and its influence and reception are also (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  27.  78
    Using Ethical Reasoning to Amplify the Reach and Resonance of Professional Codes of Conduct in Training Big Data Scientists.Rochelle E. Tractenberg, Andrew J. Russell, Gregory J. Morgan, Kevin T. FitzGerald, Jeff Collmann, Lee Vinsel, Michael Steinmann & Lisa M. Dolling - 2015 - Science and Engineering Ethics 21 (6):1485-1507.
    The use of Big Data—however the term is defined—involves a wide array of issues and stakeholders, thereby increasing numbers of complex decisions around issues including data acquisition, use, and sharing. Big Data is becoming a significant component of practice in an ever-increasing range of disciplines; however, since it is not a coherent “discipline” itself, specific codes of conduct for Big Data users and researchers do not exist. While many institutions have created, or will create, training opportunities to prepare people to (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  28.  6
    Brexit and Trump: Which Theory of Social Stasis and Social Change Copes Best With the New Populism?Chuma Kevin Owuamalam, Mark Rubin & Russell Spears - 2022 - Frontiers in Psychology 13.
    Why do voters seek to change the political landscape or to retain it? System justification theory proposes that a separate system motive to preserve the existing order drives support for the status-quo, and that this motivation operates independently from personal and collective interests. But how does this explanation apply to recent populist shifts in the political order such as Brexit and the emergence of Donald Trump? While the system motive may seem useful in understanding why the usual progressives may want (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  29.  15
    Defining area at risk and its effect in catastrophe loss estimation: a dasymetric mapping approach.Keping Chen, John McAneney, Russell Blong, Roy Leigh, Laraine Hunter & Christina Magill - 2004 - In Antoine Bailly & Lay James Gibson (eds.), Applied Geography: A World Perspective. Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 97-117.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  30. Russell's Logicism.Kevin C. Klement - 2018 - In Russell Wahl (ed.), The Bloomsbury Companion to Bertrand Russell. London, UK: BloomsburyAcademic. pp. 151-178.
    Bertrand Russell was one of the best-known proponents of logicism: the theory that mathematics reduces to, or is an extension of, logic. Russell argued for this thesis in his 1903 The Principles of Mathematics and attempted to demonstrate it formally in Principia Mathematica (PM 1910–1913; with A. N. Whitehead). Russell later described his work as a further “regressive” step in understanding the foundations of mathematics made possible by the late 19th century “arithmetization” of mathematics and Frege’s logical definitions of arithmetical (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  31. Russell's Paradox in Appendix B of the Principles of Mathematics : Was Frege's response adequate?Kevin C. Klement - 2001 - History and Philosophy of Logic 22 (1):13-28.
    In their correspondence in 1902 and 1903, after discussing the Russell paradox, Russell and Frege discussed the paradox of propositions considered informally in Appendix B of Russell’s Principles of Mathematics. It seems that the proposition, p, stating the logical product of the class w, namely, the class of all propositions stating the logical product of a class they are not in, is in w if and only if it is not. Frege believed that this paradox was avoided within his philosophy (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  32. Russell, His Paradoxes, and Cantor's Theorem: Part I.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (1):16-28.
    In these articles, I describe Cantor’s power-class theorem, as well as a number of logical and philosophical paradoxes that stem from it, many of which were discovered or considered (implicitly or explicitly) in Bertrand Russell’s work. These include Russell’s paradox of the class of all classes not members of themselves, as well as others involving properties, propositions, descriptive senses, class-intensions, and equivalence classes of coextensional properties. Part I focuses on Cantor’s theorem, its proof, how it can be used to manufacture (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  33. Russell, His Paradoxes, and Cantor's Theorem: Part II.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Philosophy Compass 5 (1):29-41.
    Sequel to Part I. In these articles, I describe Cantor’s power-class theorem, as well as a number of logical and philosophical paradoxes that stem from it, many of which were discovered or considered (implicitly or explicitly) in Bertrand Russell’s work. These include Russell’s paradox of the class of all classes not members of themselves, as well as others involving properties, propositions, descriptive senses, class-intensions and equivalence classes of coextensional properties. Part II addresses Russell’s own various attempts to solve these paradoxes, (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  34. The functions of Russell’s no class theory.Kevin C. Klement - 2010 - Review of Symbolic Logic 3 (4):633-664.
    Certain commentators on Russell's “no class” theory, in which apparent reference to classes or sets is eliminated using higher-order quantification, including W. V. Quine and (recently) Scott Soames, have doubted its success, noting the obscurity of Russell’s understanding of so-called “propositional functions”. These critics allege that realist readings of propositional functions fail to avoid commitment to classes or sets (or something equally problematic), and that nominalist readings fail to meet the demands placed on classes by mathematics. I show that Russell (...)
    Direct download (11 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  35. Russell's 1903 - 1905 Anticipation of the Lambda Calculus.Kevin C. Klement - 2003 - History and Philosophy of Logic 24 (1):15-37.
    It is well known that the circumflex notation used by Russell and Whitehead to form complex function names in Principia Mathematica played a role in inspiring Alonzo Church's “lambda calculus” for functional logic developed in the 1920s and 1930s. Interestingly, earlier unpublished manuscripts written by Russell between 1903–1905—surely unknown to Church—contain a more extensive anticipation of the essential details of the lambda calculus. Russell also anticipated Schönfinkel's combinatory logic approach of treating multiargument functions as functions having other functions as value. (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  36. Russell on Ontological Fundamentality and Existence.Kevin C. Klement - 2018 - In Landon D. C. Elkind & Gregory Landini (eds.), The Philosophy of Logical Atomism: A Centenary Reappraisal. New York, NY, USA: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 155–79.
    Russell is often taken as a forerunner of the Quinean position that “to be is to be the value of a bound variable”, whereupon the ontological commitment of a theory is given by what it quantifies over. Among other reasons, Russell was among the first to suggest that all existence statements should be analyzed by means of existential quantification. That there was more to Russell’s metaphysics than what existential quantifications come out as true is obvious in the earlier period where (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37. The Russell–Dummett Correspondence on Frege and his Nachlaß.Kevin C. Klement - 2014 - The Bertrand Russell Society Bulletin 150:25–29.
    Russell corresponded with Sir Michael Dummett (1925–2011) between 1953 and 1963 while the latter was working on a book on Frege, eventually published as Frege: Philosophy of Language (1973). In their letters they discuss Russell’s correspondence with Frege, translating it into English, as well as Frege’s attempted solution to Russell’s paradox in the appendix to vol. 2 of his Grundgesetze der Arithmetik. After Dummett visited the University of Münster to view Frege’s Nachlaß, he sent reports back to Russell concerning both (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. Early Russell on Types and Plurals.Kevin C. Klement - 2014 - Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (6):1-21.
    In 1903, in _The Principles of Mathematics_ (_PoM_), Russell endorsed an account of classes whereupon a class fundamentally is to be considered many things, and not one, and used this thesis to explicate his first version of a theory of types, adding that it formed the logical justification for the grammatical distinction between singular and plural. The view, however, was short-lived; rejected before _PoM_ even appeared in print. However, aside from mentions of a few misgivings, there is little evidence about (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  39. Russell's paradox.Kevin C. Klement - 2001 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    Russell's paradox represents either of two interrelated logical antinomies. The most commonly discussed form is a contradiction arising in the logic of sets or classes. Some classes (or sets) seem to be members of themselves, while some do not. The class of all classes is itself a class, and so it seems to be in itself. The null or empty class, however, must not be a member of itself. However, suppose that we can form a class of all classes (or (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  40. Russell-Myhill paradox.Kevin C. Klement - 2003 - Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
    The Russell-Myhill Antinomy, also known as the Principles of Mathematics Appendix B Paradox, is a contradiction that arises in the logical treatment of classes and "propositions", where "propositions" are understood as mind-independent and language-independent logical objects. If propositions are treated as objectively existing objects, then they can be members of classes. But propositions can also be about classes, including classes of propositions. Indeed, for each class of propositions, there is a proposition stating that all propositions in that class are true. (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  41. Peano, Frege and Russell’s Logical Influences.Kevin C. Klement - forthcoming - Forthcoming.
    This chapter clarifies that it was the works Giuseppe Peano and his school that first led Russell to embrace symbolic logic as a tool for understanding the foundations of mathematics, not those of Frege, who undertook a similar project starting earlier on. It also discusses Russell’s reaction to Peano’s logic and its influence on his own. However, the chapter also seeks to clarify how and in what ways Frege was influential on Russell’s views regarding such topics as classes, functions, meaning (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  42. Neo-Logicism and Russell's Logicism.Kevin C. Klement - 2012 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 32 (2):127-159.
    Certain advocates of the so-called “neo-logicist” movement in the philosophy of mathematics identify themselves as “neo-Fregeans” (e.g., Hale and Wright), presenting an updated and revised version of Frege’s form of logicism. Russell’s form of logicism is scarcely discussed in this literature and, when it is, often dismissed as not really logicism at all (in light of its assumption of axioms of infinity, reducibility and so on). In this paper I have three aims: firstly, to identify more clearly the primary meta-ontological (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  43. The paradoxes and Russell's theory of incomplete symbols.Kevin C. Klement - 2014 - Philosophical Studies 169 (2):183-207.
    Russell claims in his autobiography and elsewhere that he discovered his 1905 theory of descriptions while attempting to solve the logical and semantic paradoxes plaguing his work on the foundations of mathematics. In this paper, I hope to make the connection between his work on the paradoxes and the theory of descriptions and his theory of incomplete symbols generally clearer. In particular, I argue that the theory of descriptions arose from the realization that not only can a class not be (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  44. Higher-Order Metaphysics in Frege and Russell.Kevin C. Klement - 2024 - In Peter Fritz & Nicholas K. Jones (eds.), Higher-Order Metaphysics. Oxford University Press. pp. 355-377.
    This chapter explores the metaphysical views about higher-order logic held by two individuals responsible for introducing it to philosophy: Gottlob Frege (1848–1925) and Bertrand Russell (1872–1970). Frege understood a function at first as the remainder of the content of a proposition when one component was taken out or seen as replaceable by others, and later as a mapping between objects. His logic employed second-order quantifiers ranging over such functions, and he saw a deep division in nature between objects and functions. (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Russell on "Disambiguating with the Grain".Kevin C. Klement - 2001 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 21 (2).
    Fregeans face the difficulty finding a notation for distinguishing statements about the sense or meaning of an expression as opposed to its reference or denotation. Famously, in "On Denoting", Russell rejected methods that begin with an expression designating its denotation, and then alter it with a "the meaning of" operator to designate the meaning. Such methods attempt an impossible "backward road" from denotation to meaning. Contemporary neo-Fregeans, however, have suggested that we can disambiguate _with_, rather than _against_, the grain, by (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46. Putting form before function: Logical grammar in Frege, Russell, and Wittgenstein.Kevin C. Klement - 2004 - Philosophers' Imprint 4:1-47.
    The positions of Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein on the priority of complexes over (propositional) functions are sketched, challenging those who take the "judgment centered" aspects of the Tractatus to be inherited from Frege not Russell. Frege's views on the priority of judgments are problematic, and unlike Wittgenstein's. Russell's views on these matters, and their development, are discussed in detail, and shown to be more sophisticated than usually supposed. Certain misreadings of Russell, including those regarding the relationship between propositional functions and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  47.  10
    A metaphysics for the study of religion: A critical reading of Russell McCutcheon.Kevin Schilbrack - 2020 - Critical Research on Religion 8 (1):87-100.
    Russell McCutcheon is one of the foremost proponents of what he calls “the critical study of religion,” that is, the shift to reflect critically on the concepts used in the academic study of religion, who invented them, and why. The critical study of religion leads to the realization that the concepts with which we think were invented by particular people, at a particular historical location, for a particular purpose. What are the philosophical implications of this? McCutcheon defends a debunking or (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  48. Logical Form and the Development of Russell’s Logicism.Kevin C. Klement - 2022 - In F. Boccuni & A. Sereni (eds.), Origins and Varieties of Logicism. Routledge. pp. 147–166.
    Logicism is the view that mathematical truths are logical truths. But a logical truth is commonly thought to be one with a universally valid form. The form of “7 > 5” would appear to be the same as “4 > 6”. Yet one is a mathematical truth, and the other not a truth at all. To preserve logicism, we must maintain that the two either are different subforms of the same generic form, or that their forms are not at all (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49. The Origins of the Propositional Functions Version of Russell's Paradox.Kevin C. Klement - 2004 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 24 (2):101–132.
    Russell discovered the classes version of Russell's Paradox in spring 1901, and the predicates version near the same time. There is a problem, however, in dating the discovery of the propositional functions version. In 1906, Russell claimed he discovered it after May 1903, but this conflicts with the widespread belief that the functions version appears in _The Principles of Mathematics_, finished in late 1902. I argue that Russell's dating was accurate, and that the functions version does not appear in the (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  50. Russell's Logicism through Kantian Spectacles [review of Anssi Korhonen, Logic as Universal Science: Russell’s Early Logicism and Its Philosophical Context ].Kevin C. Klement - 2014 - Russell: The Journal of Bertrand Russell Studies 34 (1):79-84.
    Review of Logic as Universal Science: Russell’s Early Logicism and Its Philosophical Context, by Anssi Korhonen (Palgrave Macmillan 2013).
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000